Article Text

Download PDFPDF

Dissociative psychopathology, non-epileptic seizures, and neurology
  1. RICHARD J BROWN,
  2. MICHAEL R TRIMBLE
  1. Raymond Way Neuropsychiatry Research Group, University Department of Clinical Neurology, Institute of Neurology, Queen Square, London WC1N 3BG, UK
  1. Professor Michael R Trimble mtrimble{at}ionucl.ac.uk

Statistics from Altmetric.com

Request Permissions

If you wish to reuse any or all of this article please use the link below which will take you to the Copyright Clearance Center’s RightsLink service. You will be able to get a quick price and instant permission to reuse the content in many different ways.

The latest edition of the International Classification of Diseases (ICD-10)1 defines dissociation as “ . . . a partial or complete loss of the normal integration between memories of the past, awareness of identity and immediate sensations, and control of body movements” (p 151). Thus defined, the concept of dissociation captures a heterogeneous group of psychiatric conditions previously subsumed within the broader construct of hysteria. Thedissociative (conversion) disorders category in ICD-10 comprises subcategories of dissociative amnesia, dissociative fugue, trance and possession disorders, dissociative anaesthesia and sensory loss, dissociative motor disorders and dissociative convulsions, and waste basket categories included to capture uncommon, impure, or less severe instances of dissociation. Other symptoms previously viewed as hysterical are placed within thesomatoform disorders category of ICD-10, on the grounds that their primary characteristic is an apparent disturbance of bodily rather than cerebral function. By contrast, DSM-IV2 classifies convulsions, motor dysfunction, and sensory loss as somatoform disorders, despite adopting an otherwise similar definition of dissociation and categorisation of dissociative complaints. In the context of this editorial we embrace the more inclusive scheme offered by ICD-10.

The basis for their inclusion within current psychiatric nosology is the assumption that dissociative disorders are primarily psychological in nature.1 Nevertheless, the concept of dissociation has important implications for practice and research within the neurological sphere also. Dissociative psychopathology was witnessed almost exclusively within the neurological setting until the late 19th and early 20th centuries, and many such patients present to neurologists even now. What is striking about dissociative symptoms is their apparent similarity to those found in many common neurological conditions, and it is often extremely difficult to distinguish between the two; the case of dissociative convulsions provides an instructive example.

Dissociative convulsions (non-epileptic seizures)

Recent estimates suggest that between 9% and 50% of patients referred to specialist epilepsy centres have paroxysmal events that, despite resembling true epileptic episodes, are actually non-epileptic.3 In some instances, patients with reliably established epilepsy exhibit additional seizures of apparently unknown origin, although many patients may present exclusively with these so called non-epileptic attacks.4 Although some non-epileptic seizures may be attributable to physical causes other than epilepsy,5 a demonstrable organic basis is absent in many such patients, suggesting that psychological factors are instrumental in their pathogenesis. Of these cases, a proportion may be associated with an identifiable psychiatric illness such as psychosis or depression that may account for the seizure-like symptoms (for example, depressive fugue).5 A significant number, however, present with so called “pseudoseizures” or dissociative convulsions, as an isolated psychiatric condition in its own right; it is the recognition of these cases that represents a particular challenge to neurologists working within this domain.

There is no completely reliable set of procedures for identifying dissociative attacks and distinguishing them from epileptic events can be an extremely difficult task.6 As a result, many patients with dissociative attacks have received an erroneous diagnosis of epilepsy, a misjudgement that can have far reaching implications. Anticonvulsant medication misprescribed to non-epileptic patients has potentially serious side effects and may even exacerbate dissociative seizures7; failure to recognise the psychological nature of such events also delays the implementation of appropriate treatment strategies. Furthermore, the social stigma attached to a diagnosis of epilepsy is considerable. Patients who have endured such stigma for any length of time may, understandably, become hostile when informed of a diagnostic change stating that their seizures are dissociative rather than epileptic in nature.

The diagnosis of dissociative attacks requires the exclusion of epilepsy and other physical disorders; indeed, DSM-IV places dissociative convulsions in the somatoform rather than the dissociative disorders category to emphasis the importance of excluding physical illness in the differential diagnosis of these episodes.2Several factors should be considered in the diagnostic process and judgements should always be based on converging lines of evidence. A three pronged approach comprising adequate EEG, a description of preictal, ictal, and postictal events, and careful clinical history taking is the best strategy in the first instance.

The absence of ictal EEG discharges characteristic of epilepsy is a good sign that an attack is non-epileptic in nature although this may not be true for some partial seizures, particularly those originating in the frontal lobes.8 It is also important to note that “epileptic-like” interictal EEG patterns may be found in up to 3% of healthy people,9 demonstrating that an abnormal interictal EEG is often unhelpful and may even be positively misleading. Indeed, evidence of abnormal interictal EEG has been found in 20%-25% of patients with non-epileptic attacks.10 11Findings are often of abnormal temporal theta, which may be unilateral or bilateral, sometimes with sharp components. Rhythms are often paroxysmal and may acquire the much abused epithet “epileptiform”, rapidly concretised to “epileptic”, thus increasing the likelihood of subsequent misdiagnosis.

A clear and accurate clinical description, or preferably a video recording, of ictal and postictal activity is obviously an important element in the differential diagnosis of seizures. Such records can provide information on the neurological plausibility of ictal events and, in certain cases, indicate whether dissociative attacks are likely.12 Video recordings in particular are useful for determining the congruence between an individual attack occurring in the hospital or laboratory and those typically displayed by the patient in everyday life. Simultaneous video and EEG recording (video-EEG telemetry) is one of the most useful techniques as it allows for the correlation of observable seizure activity with brain electrophysiology. In addition, telemetry is extremely useful for assessing whether ictal EEG changes are cerebrally derived or artifactually produced by episode related movements.

Although video-EEG telemetry has revolutionised the diagnosis of seizures, it is an expensive procedure, and is not widely available. Moreover, many patients will not experience a typical episode during the monitoring period, particularly if the interval between seizures is long.6 There are techniques to provoke seizures that could address this problem although, in certain cases, their use remains highly controversial.6 Sleep deprivation and photic stimulation are generally regarded as ethical but may not be effective. Other techniques involve “suggesting” seizures using, for example, a placebo injection or hypnosis, which the patient is told will automatically provoke an attack. Seizures triggered using this and similar techniques are then compared with the patient's typical attacks and, assuming a match is found, the video-EEG record can be used for diagnostic purposes. Although suggestive techniques can successfully generate seizures in many cases,6 the use of deception of this sort is considered unethical by many clinicians and it is not widely used in the United Kingdom for this reason. It is also important to note that the suggestibility of a seizure is not, in itself, a reliable guide to diagnosis, as both epileptic and non-epileptic attacks can be provoked using these techniques. Moreover, contrary to established clinical lore, there is little systematic evidence demonstrating that those with dissociative attacks are any more suggestible than those with epilepsy.

Other clinical features associated with the ictus have also been offered as potentially useful diagnostic indicators,13 14although there has been little agreement across researchers and empirical findings have proved inconsistent.12 Moreover, there is no such thing as a “typical” non-epileptic seizure; whereas some ictal features may be suggestive of a particular diagnosis,12 the practical value of these features should be viewed with at least a degree of scepticism. It is also necessary to be alert to the possible unreliability of third party descriptions of seizure related events. Such descriptions are typically given by friends, relatives, or other lay persons whose reports are easily tailored to the enquiring physician's expectations.

Careful clinical history taking is also a central element in the assessment of seizures. It is important to appreciate, however, that alteration of consciousness is not uncommon in patients with non-epileptic seizures and such a history cannot therefore provide an adequate foundation for a diagnosis of epilepsy.15 Age of seizure onset may be a useful diagnostic indicator, with late onset being suggestive of a non-epileptic basis, especially if an MRI is normal.6 16 Sexual or physical abuse may be common in patients with dissociative attacks and should be sensitively enquired about17 18; given the potential for underreporting, repression and so called false memories one should, however, be judicious in accepting the face validity of any such reports. Practitioners should also bear in mind that epilepsy itself may arise from cerebral pathology sustained through childhood physical abuse and should exercise caution accordingly.

Other clinical features have been associated with dissociative seizures, although such features cannot by themselves be regarded as sufficient for an inclusive diagnosis of non-organic pathology. Potentially suggestive of a dissociative diagnosis are a personal and family history of psychiatric illness and the presence of comorbid psychopathology,19 a family history of epilepsy,19 and evidence of clear psychosocial seizure precipitants.1 2 Raised postictal serum prolactin concentrations (greater than 1000 IU/l) in the presence of normal baseline values are found after epileptic seizures,20although this is limited to certain seizure types21; moreover, false positives can occur (for example, with syncope). Self injury is common in both epileptic and dissociative seizures, although the site and severity of lesions often differ between the two. Carpet burns, for example, are almost always indicative of non-epileptic attacks. The presence of other dissociative “stigmata”, such as unexplained sensory loss, may also support a non-epileptic diagnosis. On the other hand, incontinence is typically a poor guide to seizure type.

The ease with which epileptic and dissociative events are confused, coupled with the serious implications of misdiagnosis, demonstrates that physicians must be aware of the various clinical phenomena that may present as epileptic and non-epileptic seizures, and the converging lines of evidence that are required before a firm diagnosis can be made in either direction. Making a diagnosis is clearly a complex and difficult process that requires an experienced clinician, with both neurological and psychiatric knowledge, and the support of adequate EEG and neuroimaging facilities. As in so many areas of medicine, the more quickly a firm diagnosis can be established, the better the prognosis.22

Presenting the diagnosis of dissociative seizures

Once a firm diagnosis has been reached, presenting that diagnosis to the individual patient is the first, and one of the most important, parts of treatment. Considerable care needs to be taken at this point, especially when a previous, incorrect diagnosis has been in place for some time. Contrary to what many neurologists think, a patient is unlikely to be jubilant to discover that their seizures, previously identified as epileptic, are actually dissociative in nature. In the first instance, patients are likely to be upset that they have been given an erroneous diagnosis in the first place, particularly as they may have encountered prejudice as a result of the epileptic label. Secondly, most patients will be angry if they have been given unnecessary medication, especially if unpleasant drug side effects have had a large impact on their quality of life. Thirdly, coming to terms with the psychiatric diagnosis itself is difficult for many patients, who often think that their suffering is being dismissed as “all in their mind” or, worse still, deliberately faked for secondary gain. Although there are cases where seizures have been consciously simulated (“malingering”), such cases are rare except in certain settings. Unless there is good reason to suspect simulation (for example, impending legal claim coupled with an evasive attitude to assessment and an inconsistent seizure presentation/clinical history etc), it should be assumed that the events are subjectively genuine and treated accordingly.

The diagnosis of dissociative seizures is ideally presented by a psychiatrist or neuropsychiatrist who is a member of the team involved in the patient's care. To begin with, the patient should be informed of the positive news that their attacks are not the result of cerebral damage and abnormal brain activity and are not, therefore, epileptic in nature.23 At this point, they should be told that anticonvulsant medication will be of no benefit to them and, if they are taking any such medication, that it should be withdrawn slowly but as soon as possible. In some cases, showing the patient the video-EEG record on which their diagnosis was based may help them to accept the non-epileptic nature of their attacks. Patients should then be gently introduced to the notion that their seizures are caused by psychological rather than neurological factors. Resistance to this idea may be reduced if it is emphasised that such a diagnosis does not mean that their seizures are “faked” or that they are any less real or distressing than “genuine” epileptic attacks; patients should also be reassured that the diagnosis does not mean that they are “insane” or “crazy” (assuming the absence of other significant psychiatric problems). Many patients will raise the legitimate question of how it is possible for their attacks to be psychological when they are unaware of any emotional upset or psychological problems, or any link between such problems and their seizures. The clinician should use such an opportunity to introduce the idea that dissociative seizures are normally caused by unconscious psychological processes, emphasising the role of such processes in normal behaviour and giving everyday examples (see Devinsky and Thacker22) where possible. Examples demonstrating the close link between mind and body (for example, palms sweating when nervous) may be particularly useful in this respect.

For many patients, coming to terms with a psychological explanation for their attacks will be far from easy. As such, presenting the diagnosis of dissociative seizures in a confrontational manner is unlikely to be of use and will increase resistance to the diagnosis in many cases. Rather, the clinician should be as supportive and reassuring as possible, emphasising that psychological attacks often have a better prognosis than those associated with epilepsy. Careful use of terminology is extremely important and certain expressions should be avoided. The term “pseudoseizure”, for example, often meets with resistance as it seems to imply that the patient's seizures are faked. Also to be avoided are the terms “hysteria” and “hysterical”, which are pejorative and have acquired lay connotations that are entirely misleading. In our experience, patients also strongly object to being informed that their seizures are “all in the mind” or “imaginary”. We think that the term “non-epileptic attacks” is probably the most appropriate in this context as it is accurate, theoretically neutral, and acknowledges the authenticity of the patient's complaint. Such an approach allows the patient to accept the diagnosis while saving face, something that is particularly important in the context of the patient's interaction with their family and wider social circle. Indeed, in many cases it is desirable, where permission has been given, for the clinician to inform members of the patient's family of the non-epileptic diagnosis also.

Treatment issues

Once the diagnosis of dissociative convulsions has been presented, treatment can begin. Depending on the patient, some form of psychological therapy is typically the approach of choice, and there is limited evidence indicating the efficacy of such a treatment strategy.16 24 However, there are few, if any, adequately controlled studies addressing this issue empirically. Ideally, treatment will be conducted by a psychiatrist, psychologist, or psychotherapist who is part of the multidisciplinary team involved in the patient's care from the outset. Where this is not possible, the referring physician should remain involved to some degree so that the patient does not feel “abandoned in the hands of a psychiatrist”.23

To begin with, the presence of comorbid clinical anxiety or depression should be addressed, often with pharmacotherapy. Psychological therapy should then be considered, with the specific approach depending largely on the nature of the individual patient and the presenting problem. In some cases, psychotherapy addressing the emotional issues surrounding the occurrence of dissociative events may be of some use. However, such an approach requires a certain degree of insight and psychological mindedness on behalf of the patient and not all patients have the capacity to face the emotional demands made by this sort of treatment. Cognitive and behavioural approaches aimed at identifying and controlling the factors precipitating and maintaining dissociative seizures are less demanding than psychotherapy and seem to work in many cases. Behavioural approaches seem particularly well suited to the treatment of those with a learning disability, and/or where secondary gain seems to be an important maintaining factor. In many cases, family therapy may also be an important aspect of treatment, particularly where a dysfunctional family dynamic seems to be contributing to the occurrence of the dissociative attacks.22 Some clinicians also advocate the use of hypnosis as an adjunct to the psychological therapy of these patients.22 Such an approach may be of some use, although the patient's beliefs about hypnosis and their attitude towards it should be carefully explored before proceeding.

The few studies considering treatment outcome in patients with dissociative attacks16 24 suggest that the prognosis of these patients is actually fairly good, given careful psychological management and early diagnosis. However, there is a desperate need for well controlled, systematic studies comparing the various treatment approaches to dissociative attacks and assessing the factors predicting positive outcome.

Understanding and operationalising dissociation

The confusion surrounding the differential diagnosis of non-epileptic seizures provides just one example of the challenge that dissociation represents within neurological practice. As the dissociative disorders categories of ICD-10 and DSM-IV indicate, the symptoms of many neurological conditions have a dissociative counterpart. Thus, both neurological and psychiatric examples of amnesia, fugue states, motor problems, sensory loss, stupor, and coma have been described, with the list apparently only limited by the number of neurological symptoms currently subject to classification. In many such cases, practitioners attempting to separate dissociative from organic phenomena encounter the same diagnostic dilemma as that discussed here for epilepsy and non-epileptic seizures.

The principle problem in this context is that the diagnosis of dissociation is primarily based on the exclusion of organic pathology rather than the preferred set of psychiatric inclusion criteria. Identifying such criteria promises to be a laborious task requiring a degree of conceptual and methodological sophistication at present lacking in this domain. Current theory concerning the dissociative disorders continues to be dominated by the ideas of Janet25 and his conceptual successor Hilgard,26 and many Freudian27 concepts also remain popular. Such accounts are, however, vague and do not lend themselves well to empirical evaluation,28 leading to a descriptive rather than a mechanistic understanding of the term “dissociation”.29 The shortcomings of existing theory and research are well illustrated by a recent study30attempting to distinguish organic and non-organic epileptic events using the dissociative experiences scale (DES),31 a putative operationalisation of dissociation. Although dissociative (non-epileptic) patients would be expected to report more dissociation than their non-dissociative (epileptic) counterparts, total DES scores were not significantly different between these groups,30despite being relatively high in both cases. Moreover, any modest differences on DES factor or item scores appeared attributable to discrepancies in sexual and physical abuse reported by epileptic and non-epileptic patients. Thus, whereas patients with so called dissociative psychopathology have “dissociative” experiences as part of their clinical presentation, this study clearly demonstrated that patients with non-dissociative, organic pathology also have such experiences, at least as measured by the DES. Indeed, a recent review by Good32 suggests that dissociative experiences may be common in other physical conditions, demonstrating the existence of so called “organic dissociation” akin to the concept of “organic repression” suggested by Schilder33 many years ago.

Although measures such as the DES allow us to assess the degree to which patients experience apparent disruptions in consciousness, memory, identity, or control, they do not provide a means for evaluating which processes, psychiatric or neurological, actually underlie any supposed episode of “dissociation”. Clearly, we need to move beyond the descriptive approach to dissociation inspired by existing theoretical models,25-27 advocated by current classificatory schemes1 2 and embodied by measures such as the DES. To do this, the first goal must be to provide a precise definition of dissociation based on a conceptually coherent and empirically justified account of the processes underlying these phenomena. Armed with such a definition, we may turn to the critical task of constructing a satisfactory operationalisation of dissociation that serves to define the criteria for an inclusive diagnosis of dissociative psychopathology. After such a process it is likely that many of the phenomena previously identified as dissociative, such as epilepsy related memory loss, will no longer be viewed as dissociative at all!

In our view, neurology will have an important part to play in the development of any satisfactory theoretical account of the mechanisms underlying dissociative psychopathology. To this end, Whitlock34 and Ludwig35 have suggested that the primary pathophysiological mechanism involved in the creation and maintenance of dissociative (or “hysterical”) symptoms is an attentional dysfunction resulting from an increase in the corticofugal inhibition of afferent stimulation. As a result of this inhibition, partially processed stimulus information fails to be integrated into on going awareness, generating dissociative symptoms as a consequence. Some studies have provided empirical support for this account of dissociation.36 37 Part of the appeal of the approach advocated by investigators such as Ludwig is their emphasis on integrating research and theory from neurology, psychiatry, and psychology in a bid to understand the mechanisms of dissociation.

Acknowledgments

This work should be attributed to the University Department of Clinical Neurology, Institute of Neurology, London. This work is supported by the Raymond Way Neuropsychiatry Research Group fund.

References